Why You Shouldn’t Believe Anything You’re Told – 3.2
3.2 More solid resistance to idealism? – the case of the orthodox applied sciences.
Anti-idealism has been slow to develop in sociology as the recent flirtation with postmodernism suggests. However, another area of formal resistance to ideals such as uncertainty involves applied sciences such as engineering and medicine. There is nothing exact about measurement; it is all about estimation – the steel girder is 5 metres long, plus or minus 1 millimetre, the drug has only a small chance of harming you if it has been tested using randomized trials, even though catastrophe such as death can still occur. The sciences that deal in measurement are very reality-oriented and specify their findings in terms of probabilities not proofs, in stark contrast with the much less reality-congruent pure sciences such as physics, chemistry and biology; the word ‘pure’ by its very nature is redolent of idealism. Why is it that applied sciences are seen as the poor relations of natural science? I believe it is their lack of idealism that explains this. They have lesser status because they are not truth-finders, they are merely the artisans who deal in day to day problems explained in terms of probabilities, whereas the physicists deal in ‘cool’, they are the dominant figuration of scientists who are the custodians of the faith because they control the thing of ultimate value as the apostles of the mathesis, the absolute truth. If people were asked to explain the workings of the universe, I would suggest that two types of answer would dominate: 1) supernatural accounts such as God 2) models developed by physicists such as Newton, Einstein even Heisenberg, although the biological Darwinian model is now a close rival.
Leaving the supernatural aside, although it must be said that in all the above there is an element of mysticism as Comte suggested, the high status accorded to physicists is I believe, constituted on the basis of their expertise and love affair with idealism in the form of pure mathematics and to a lesser extent, philosophical logic: see the work of Karl Popper. Even though this elite figuration of mathematical truth-finders has run into a red light signalled by the inability of Einstein’s model to explain the world of sub-atomic particles, physicists and theoretical scientists still insist on a mathematical discourse that speaks in terms of ideals. So, rather than ponder the possibility that the boundary between the macro-universe (stars and planets) and the micro-universe (sub-atomic particles such as baryons and quarks) is actually a problem of idealistic method, Heisenberg ingeniously revamped the old method by invoking the ‘Uncertainty Principle’ and a new mathematics. Thus in true idealistic form we have a dichotomy: we are certain about the big part of the universe and uncertain about the little bits. Instead of looking for a more reality congruent, radical model, lead by the facts, we continue re-branding the old idealism. It may well be that in reaching the limit of certainty and crossing over to the mathematics of uncertainty, we have been brought face to face with relative uncertainty because neither ends of the dichotomy are feasible – Einstein nor Heisenberg. However, to investigate the ‘Relative Uncertainty Principle’ may require the total exhaustion of the old way, (M-theory gives the impression of something akin to this happening) before a more reality congruent model can be developed.
The use of the word ‘Relative’ is very important because it distances us from the idealism of the ‘certainty-uncertainty’ dichotomy, suggesting a continuum comprised of degrees of certainty/uncertainty with no definitive limit to either. Based on my experience I would suggest that like the rest of our knowledge of the universe, the world of tiny events is not ‘Uncertain’ as per Heisenberg; it is ‘relatively uncertain’. Only mathematicians, other than God or philosophical logicians, can provide the ideals of certainty or uncertainty, to act as guides in our search for knowledge. However, the mistake is to assume that they are knowledge in themselves, when in fact they are an aid for comparison, a useful means of modelling or approximating the world. Consequently, we spend large amounts of time considering ideals and issues of certainty and uncertainty and too little on the practical problems that employ the real nuggets of knowledge provided by applied science that embrace relative uncertainty by allowing us to calculate probabilities. This may be explained by the preference of established business-oriented figurations and their allies for truth over relative certainty.
However, high reality-orientation does not immunise applied scientists from idealising infections that can paralyse their models, any more than Soviet style communist governors could eradicate religion. Social science, and more pertinently for this discussion – sociology, is I would argue, a case in point and offers further insight on the way idealism can subvert scientific goals. I think it can be argued that the development of sociology has been hampered by figurations within its ranks idealistically committed to the politics of inequality: sociology has been colonised by people whose main purpose has been to use it as a base in the battle for authority in areas such as class, sex and race. Accordingly, sociological perspectives have too often been motivated by sheer moral outrage, rather than the relative detachment necessary for scientific analysis of social problems. This is not to say that class etc. should not be researched; it is the goal of that research which is at issue. If by investigating scientifically social problems sociologists produce findings that explain relative inequality then fine. If however, research is motivated by a wish to establish the ideal of equality, it is not scientific and therefore not sociology. Such a programme motivated by the need for authority that idealism can provide will suffer from too large a dose of what theometaphysicians call subjectivity, or, what I would prefer to call, after Elias, ‘relative involvement’.
Too much research done under the auspices of sociology, especially in the field of theory, has I would argue, been carried out by people from figurations dedicated to ideals such as equality, who should have proffered their ideas as philosophy, politics (as opposed to political science), cultural theory, literary criticism or journalism. The involvement of such people, often highly influential, disrupts not only the scientific character of the discipline, but also clouds the vision of those who practice it. Perhaps the most prominent example was the importation of Marx’s philosophy into sociology, with its blend Hegelian idealism and underdeveloped science: Marxism is arguably a piece of humanitarian conviction politics, that speaks of absolute truths rather than probabilities. As opposed to benefiting from Marx’s insights by refining the scientific aspects of his model, especially his attack on idealism, too many sociologists have been preoccupied with pursuing, re-analysing and justifying his metaphysics – why is this? Because like Marx they want the authority to change the world rather than understand it in a more realistic way; their agenda is political, it is about the fight for influence to attain personal ideals, not science. Such a process is evidence of the still pervasive influence of philosophy through conceptual habits that allow us to pursue ideals disguised as science, even in a world of greater uncertainty. Thus, it is easy to exclude sociology from science and call it a branch of the humanities, subservient to the philosophers.
The problem is in part a function of the special place that sociologists inhabit in the community of scientists, because in order to establish their right to exist as bona fide members of the figuration they had a bigger fight on their hands with the traditional figurations of truth-finders: the theologians and philosophers. One of the pioneers in this process, Auguste Comte, felt the full force of their stigmatizing influence, which is ongoing, as a reading of Michel Foucault testifies who has contributed to the vilification of Comte’s concept of positivism. It was not so easy for theologians and philosophers to assimilate sociologists into their ranks as they had the physicists, because sociologists were immediately identifiable as rivals, competing for dominance in the same field of expertise – human moral knowledge. The threat posed by earlier natural scientific figurations to the old orders of truth-finders was met with fierce resistance, as the likes of Copernicus and Galileo found out. However, as we now know the development of scientific figurations could not be stopped, even by the still formidable Roman Catholic Church, as the more reality-focused business-oriented figurations became more influential. The natural philosophers (early scientists) were I would suggest ameliorated, a job made easier because the natural philosophers were claiming expertise over the relatively uncolonised ground of the material universe, Genesis apart. Nevertheless, their activities were closely chaperoned by the ancient truth-finders, to produce a new amalgam of knowledge that mixed together theology, philosophy, mathematics and science – deism. In contrast, sociologists were a threat of a more serious order on account of the fact that they were disputing ownership of the same area of knowledge. Just as later scientists such as the figuration headed by Darwin have attracted so much fierce resistance, sociologists have been subjected to very aggressive attempts to undermine and discredit their approach.
It was arguably not until the 19th century that the threat from natural scientists became truly manifest, with the emergence of a historicized scientific account of life forms in the shape of the Darwinian model. The arrival of the de-theologized theory of natural selection, has attracted very intense anti-scientific resistance from the start, which arguably continues to provoke unrest as the attempt to reassert the various theological orthodoxies by contemporary groups of religious fundamentalists testifies. The emergence of sociology was a pre-cursor to these hostilities, as a historicized science intruding onto the hallowed ground of human morals. The birth of anything is fraught with problems, made only worse if the new arrival is perceived to be a direct threat to the established: the reaction in ancient Egypt to the arrival of Moses springs to light as a mythical example. For the traditional guardians of moral knowledge, a sociological explanation undermined everything they had laboured for millennia to produce, by suggesting that knowledge was something that changed with time. Such a conclusion is anathema to the truth-finders whose raison d’être is defined by the search for stability; a programme by its very nature, resistant to a historicizing approach to knowledge. Consequently, the raw material that sociologists had to develop, inherited from the truth-finders, was almost starved of any historical content having been thoroughly scourged of such corrupt material by theologians and philosophers committed to ideals. Not only was the raw material of sociology in need of a thorough transposition, it was relatively easy to re-colonize by 20th century idealists, waiting for the first major hiccup in sociology’s theoretical development when both Parsonianism and Marxism were found wanting as what Thomas Kuhn called a ‘paradigms’.